AI and the Probability of Conflict
It is commonly argued that artificial general intelligence (AGI), unaligned with human values, represents an existential risk for humanity. For example, in his recent book The Precipice, philosopher Toby Ord argued that there is a 10 percent chance that unaligned artificial general intelligence will result in existential catastrophe for humanity. Less attention is devoted to whether or how aligned AGI could introduce additional existential risk, such as through increasing the probability of conflict.
It is commonly argued that artificial general intelligence (AGI), unaligned with human values, represents an existential risk for humanity. For example, in his recent book The Precipice, philosopher Toby Ord argued that there is a 10 percent chance that unaligned artificial general intelligence will result in existential catastrophe for humanity in the coming century.
Less attention is devoted to whether or how aligned AGI could introduce additional existential risk, such as through increasing the probability of conflict. For example, how would one country react to the news that another country is on the verge of developing an AGI fully under their control, a potential geopolitical game changer similar to the advent of nuclear weapons?
Aligned AGI could have important geopolitical implications by altering both the nature and probability of conflict. But how exactly? This is difficult to answer given that the form of AGI is still hugely uncertain. Nevertheless, the different scenarios explored below indicate that aligned AGI would not greatly increase the probability of conflict.
Let’s explore these scenarios in detail.
Setting the scene
Consider two countries, the Hegemon and the Challenger. Furthermore, assume that both countries are trying to develop AGI. How would they strategise vis-à-vis one another?
First, we need to make some assumptions about what the goals of these two states are. Let’s assume that they seek to maximise their relative power, in line with the theory of offensive realism articulated by John Mearsheimer. In other words, they care more about security than prosperity, and therefore try to ensure their independence from other powers.
Empirically speaking, this is not always true: US and European policy towards China in the 90s and 00s is but one exception to this. But states do seem to converge over time to a realist approach, while divergences from it seem to be temporary and idiosyncratic.
Now, we want to understand how both states might behave just before and after AGI is developed.
The capabilities of AGI are important to note at this point. For this, it is instructive to take a quote from Ord. After discussing how an AGI could be even more persuasive than historical demagogues in convincing others to do its will, he says:
First, the AGI system could gain access to the internet and hide thousands of backup copies, scattered among insecure computer systems around the world, ready to wake up and continue the job if the original is removed. Even by this point, the AGI would be practically impossible to destroy: consider the political obstacles to erasing all hard drives in the world where it may have backups. It could then take over millions of unsecured systems on the internet, forming a large “botnet.” This would be a vast scaling-up of computational resources and provide a platform for escalating power. From there, it could gain financial resources (hacking the bank accounts on those computers) and human resources (using blackmail or propaganda against susceptible people or just paying them with its stolen money). It would then be as powerful as a well-resourced criminal underworld, but much harder to eliminate. None of these steps involve anything mysterious—hackers and criminals with human-level intelligence have already done all of these things using just the internet. (p. 146-147)
The security implications of this kind of AGI are already serious, but Ord then goes on to discuss how such an AGI could further scale up its intelligence. Presumably it could even compromise relatively secure military systems.
At this point it might be tempting to compare the creation of AGI to the development of nuclear weapons, as one state developing it first could render other countries defenceless. But there are important differences between AGI and nuclear weapons.
First, AGI could be quite surgical in the systems it targets and compromises. Whereas a leader may be reluctant to deploy a nuclear weapon due to the immense collateral damage it would wreak, the same reluctance may not be felt when deploying an AGI.
Second, an AGI is far easier to employ discreetly. It is impossible to miss the explosion of a nuclear bomb in any populated area. But how can you know if there is an AGI lurking in your radar detection or military communications system? The hack may take place well before exploit, making it harder to know how secure your defences actually are.
How aligned AGI could alter the probability of conflict
Having set the scene, we should now ask ourselves the broadest question: would such technology make war more likely?
In an article discussing the causes of conflict, Jackson and Morelli note that the prerequisites for a war to break out between rational actors involve 1) the cost not being overwhelmingly high and 2) there being no ability to reach a mutually beneficial and enforceable agreement.
AGI would cause both 1) and 2) to change in a way that makes war more likely. The cost of conflict could fall for two reasons. First, an AGI would be costless to replicate, like any program. Second, the fact that a war could start in cyberspace may also lead to the belief that it could be contained there, meaning that there would be fewer human casualties.
But it seems that part 2) changes more radically. If AGI is sufficiently advanced, it may be undetectable, making any non-aggression pact difficult to enforce. Moreover, the fact that AGI as software is essentially costless to replicate would allow the aggressor to choose unexpected and obscure targets: it may make sense to disrupt a competitor by being a nuisance in countless small ways, something which would not have been feasible when intelligent manpower was quite scarce.
There is therefore good reason to think that AGI would increase the probability of war. But this brief analysis is flawed, as it does not take into account the fact the possibility that AGI could self-improve at a rate that would render any rivals uncompetitive—a scenario known as fast take-off, under which would the probability of war would probably fall.
AGI: Fast take-off
If AGI is marked by fast take-off, this implies that one country would gain a decisive and permanent lead.
If the Hegemon attains this lead, there is probably little that the Challenger could do to stop it. As the weaker party, a pre-emptive strike would not be a feasible option. The Challenger could try to insulate itself from external influence, but they would be racing against time if the Hegemon became determined to assert its power. At a minimum, the Challenger would need some defensive systems to be completely free from digital interference. But even then, AGI could boost the capabilities of conventional kinetic weapons to such a degree such that that cyber-insulation would be futile.
A slightly more interesting scenario is if the Challenger is on the verge of developing AGI, and is closer to this than the Hegemon. Would the Hegemon launch a pre-emptive strike to maintain its superior position? This is quite similar to the dilemma the US faced as the Soviets developed their nuclear capability. At the time, some such as John von Neumann and Bertrand Russell were in favour of such a pre-emptive strike. Given the extreme costs of that, US leadership shied away from following it through.
The calculus for the hegemon would be less favourable in the context of AGI because it does not possess a decisive strategic advantage: other countries have nuclear capabilities, and therefore the Hegemon is vulnerable to nuclear retaliation if it tries to prevent the Challenger developing AGI. Even if the Hegemon tried to push for an agreement to prevent the development of weaponized AGI, this would unenforceable. Such agreements can partially work for nuclear weapons because testing a missile is detectable. The same would not be true for developing or testing an AGI.
At this point, it is worth noting that a fast take-off could introduce a large degree of asymmetric information: one side will know much more about its capabilities than the other side. In this context, miscalculations could be likely. Given the stakes involved, it would also not be surprising if much of this work was done in secret, in order to prevent any pre-emptive moves from the other side.
But fast take-off is simply one scenario. How would the calculus of the two states change in the context of slow take-off?
AGI: Slow take-off
Under this scenario, there would be many AGIs of broadly similar ability, with some better in some dimensions than others. Let’s assume that the two states have roughly similar levels of AGI technology.
A tenuous technological lead would decrease the incentive of launching a pre-emptive strike. So what the optimal strategy should be in this context is far less clear, if indeed there would a dominant strategy at all.
One possibility is that the overall outcome will depend upon whether offensive or defensive capabilities are greater. Bruce Schneier, noting that the status quo favours the offensive regarding cyberattacks, believes that improvements in AI will boost the defensive. The idea here is that cyberdefence is currently overly reliant on humans, whereas a computer can scan for vulnerabilities and launch attacks at speed and at scale. Growing defensive capabilities would therefore decrease the probability of an outbreak of conflict.
However, in an article for War on the Rocks, Ben Garfinkel and Allan Dafoe noted that historical attempts to guess this balance have been wrong: before WW1, it was assumed that offense had the advantage, but the opposite turned out to be true.
While these authors seem to be referring to AI rather than AGI, there are other reasons to think that a slow take-off scenario would decrease the probability of conflict.
First, if future forms of AGI differ widely, then both sides may want to prevent their knowledge falling into the hands of the other side, something presumably more likely to happen if AGI is deployed. That a qualitative race is less likely to lead to war is also an idea supported by Huntington, who theorized in a 1958 article that quantitative races are more likely to lead to war than qualitative races. This is because with qualitative races, an innovative breakthrough could jumble the ranking, whereas a quantitative race could allow a state to build a definitive and long-lasting lead. Moreover, quantitative races are more expensive, leading to greater efforts to radicalize the population against the enemy—emotions which could later force conflict.
As progress in AI is likely to be mainly qualitative, its growing importance in security matters would seem to reduce the probability of war. However, even a quantitative race could imply a lower probability of war, as Garfinkel and Dafoe stated in the article cited above. They use the example of drone swarms and cyberattacks to illustrate that while initial deployments of such technology would advantage an attacker, a continued build-up on both sides would eventually favour the defending side as they would be able to identify and plug any gaps in their defence.
At this point, it is important to note that we should be too confident in these models. Given the potentially surgical and under-the-radar nature of AGI, the nature of the conflict could also change in a way such that past models of conflict would become obsolete. For example, if we arrive at a world where AGI is undetectable and there is low differentiation in AGI forms, the emphasis may be on exploiting any vulnerability as soon as it arises. This could give rise to an attritional, under-the-radar conflict, where the objective may be to hinder the productive potential of the other side by generally being a nuisance. The point would be to do damage just below the threshold of detection, implying numerous small incidents rather than a few large strikes. This would hinder the productive potential of the opposing side, making them less threatening as a competitor in the international sphere.
If AGI takes a great deal of computational power, then this scenario could obviously result in a huge drain on resources. Perhaps one boundary on how intense that war would get would be just the strain on resources it would cause.
How would the world escape from such an equilibrium?
Walled gardens and customised infrastructures could become more common. Such a world could be less likely to feature for example the same piece of infrastructure being reused, because a breakthrough in one place would allow for a breakthrough in many places.
But for this to be feasible in geopolitical terms, there would need to be a broad equality in AGI technology across the different blocs.
Conclusion
We can draw a number of tentative conclusions from the above.
In a scenario with fast take-off, it is likely that a single state (or part thereof, such as a company) would gain the capacity to become or to control a hegemon, and it could be impossible for other states to catch up. While this would probably eliminate the possibility of a war (through either immense power of persuasion or outright coercion), states or groups that have acquired untrammelled power have rarely been benign. And history would never have seen an example so stark as this. The flaws of human nature thus leave much to be pessimistic about in this scenario.
In the event of slow take-off, different states or coalitions thereof will remain competitive. But if knowledge of the AGI capabilities of other states is opaque, and if AGI intrusions remain undetectable, then this could make war more likely due to higher amounts of asymmetric information and the greater difficulty of enforcing any agreement.
However, some characteristics of AGI could reduce the chance of war breaking out. First, AGI could eventually boost defensive capabilities more than offensive capabilities, making war (or at least cyberwar) a less attractive option for the state considering it. Second, the fact that it is more likely to trigger a qualitative race would make definitive leads less likely and incur less of a strain on the states concerned, making rallying the population less necessary.
Finally, even if we have discussed the chance of an outbreak of conflict, the form conflict could take is still unknown. In addition, the cost would greatly depend on whether cyberwar could be contained in cyberspace.
This analysis faces other limitations. The distinction between Aligned and Unaligned AGI could end up being quite fluid. As Eliezer Yudkowsky pointed out in reaction to an earlier version of this text, if alignment is obtained by placing constraints on the reward function of an AGI, then decision-makers may be tempted to relax those contraints if higher performance is needed in the context of an arms race — putting us in the dangerous world of Unaligned AGI.
**************
To receive an occasional update on articles and book reviews on this site, subscribe here.
Alternatively, you can find me on Twitter.
How Inequality Killed the Roman Republic
An increasingly familiar analysis begins with a vague tale involving rising dissatisfaction with elites, spiralling inequality, and growing political instability. The “twist” is that this describes not a modern Western society, but republican Rome. These comparisons often tend to be shallow, and therefore potentially misleading; is there anything to be learned from them? To answer this question, I turned to the book Mortal Republic: How Rome Fell into Tyranny by Edward J. Watts.
Article Summary
An increasingly familiar analysis begins with a vague tale involving rising dissatisfaction with elites, spiralling inequality, and growing political instability. The “twist” is that this describes not a modern Western society, but republican Rome. These comparisons often tend to be shallow, and therefore potentially misleading; is there anything to be learned from them? To answer this question, I turned to the book Mortal Republic: How Rome Fell into Tyranny by Edward J. Watts.
The key lessons I took from Watt’s narrative could be summarised as follows.
First, the high degree of social cohesion in early Roman Republic — the critical advantage that helped them defeat their rivals — was the result of the main source of prestige being not wealth but honours, which were completely controlled by the Republic. Elites competed for such honours by providing services to the state, thereby channelling ambition into pro-social causes. Such a system was probably possible for two reasons. First, the elite was generally small and completely based in the city of Rome. Second, it was composed of wealthy landowners among whom there was little variation in wealth. These two factors taken together probably meant that the only way to rise in status was to obtain the honours granted by state service.
Second, once Rome began to expand, wealth began to increase due to the spoils of foreign conquest and later the gains from trade. Such wealth began to make the honours bestowed by the state seem somewhat quaint. But aspirant politicians also began to use this wealth to promote themselves, such as by hosting larger gladiator games. Such self-promotion was then leveraged to win offices. This new channel of self-promotion reduced the ability of the state to first require some pro-social efforts in order to obtain an honour. Before, you could only acquire honours by doing the state some service. Later, you could really only acquire honours by first acquiring wealth.
Once wealth was used to lock-in power, power was used to lock-in wealth. This positive feedback loop eventually incurred a populist backlash, the energies of which were used by successive politicians to undermine the system, to introduce dynastic politics, and eventually to establish an autocracy.
For a political system to avoid the descent into demagoguery, it needs to prevent a positive feedback loop forming between wealth and power. While the strength of that feedback loop varies across the West, it still seems to pose difficulties in many countries. Eliminating it either requires a reduction of inequality, or else creating a mechanism to prevent people from using wealth to influence the rules and processes regarding the selection of political elites.
But breaking this loop alone cannot create a cohesive society. For that, a social reward along the lines of the Roman honours system could be useful. In the below essay, I speculate about some ideas for how this idea could be implemented in a modern society. It involves creating a bottom-up selection process in small groups. Safeguards against nepotism or dominance by the wealthy could be overseen by a group that has no monetary wealth and/or children, as such a group would not have the ability and/or incentive to favour their children.
To understand how I came to take these lessons from the book, read on.
Introduction
The ghost of the Roman Empire looms over any discussion on the fate of societies. In the last decade, the course of events has causes the number of comparisons to rise. Trump tried but failed to be a Caesar-like figure in wielding populist sentiment like a weapon against democratic norms. The Dutch prime minister, Mark Rutte, compared the 2015 European migration crisis to the Völkerwanderung that heralded the end of the Western Roman Empire.
But does the story of the very different Roman society actually have lessons for our own? To answer this question, I turned to Mortal Republic: How Rome Fell into Tyranny by Edward J. Watts, Professor of History at the University of California, San Diego. It outlines in detail the events that led to Rome transitioning from essentially a highly cohesive aristocracy to the oligarchic autocracy founded by Augustus. The story starts not when Rome was at its most extensive, but when it was most cohesive — for it was this cohesion that enabled the rapid expansion that would come later.
A Demonstration of Roman Social Cohesion
In 280 BC, after the collapse of Alexander the Great’s empire, mainland Italy was invaded by Pyrrhus, a Greek king who aimed to conquer. He won his first encounter with the Romans but at a cost of between one-sixth and one-half of his most highly trained soldiers. Despite being victorious, he could not continue to sustain such losses. Even worse for Pyrrhus, he couldn’t win the allegiance of any significant Roman allies in the south of Italy, and the Romans had no difficulty in replacing any killed or injured soldiers. He therefore needed to negotiate with the Romans.
His strategy for this negotiation included lenient terms and expensive presents. The Romans were initially close to accepting this offer but ultimately rejected it as the humiliation of defeat could have put Roman hegemony over Italy at risk, resulting in more threats in the future.
The formidability of the Romans became more apparent in the course of a negotiation over the exchange of prisoners. Noting that the Roman interlocutor, Fabricius, was relatively poor, Pyrrhus decided to offer Fabricius “so much silver and gold that he would be able to surpass all the Romans who are said to be most wealthy.” Fabricius refused the offer and Watts recounts his reply as follows:
Fabricius, we are told, responded to Pyrrhus by informing him that his assumption was incorrect. Though he did not possess great material wealth, Fabricius told Pyrrhus, he did hold the highest offices in the state, he was sent on the most distinguished embassies, he was called upon to publicly express his opinions on the most important issues, and he was praised, envied, and honored for his uprightness. The Roman Republic, he continued, provided everyone who goes into public service with honors more splendid than any possession. It also regularly made an account of the property of Romans and could easily find anyone who had become wealthy dishonorably. What good would it do, Fabricius supposedly concluded, for him to accept gold and silver when this would cost him his honor and reputation? How could he endure a life in which he and his descendants were wealthy but disgraced?
Pyrrhus did not win and eventually left Italy for good. But the above example illustrates an interesting point. Fabricius valued honour over possessions and wealth. And more importantly, wealth could not be used to purchase honour.
Because honour could only be attained by public service, the energies of the most ambitious Romans were channelled towards the common good. According to Watt, “Romans of the third century instead judged each man’s merit by the offices he held, the honors he earned, and whether his achievements equaled those of his ancestors.” This meant that the “Republic dictated what sort of service an individual gave, it determined what sorts of rewards he would receive, and it paid these rewards out in a form of social currency that it alone controlled.”
The system of honour included a series of offices known as the cursus honorum, where at a given age one was eligible to be elected to a certain post only if one had completed a previous position. The first step involved serving 10 years in the military. After this position and on becoming 30 years of age, one was eligible to run for the position of quaestor (thereby becoming deputy to a provincial governor or a financial administrator). This would last for one year. After this and on reaching 36, one could have served as an aedile. After being an aedile or a quaestor, and being at least 39 years old, one could have run to be a praetor.
Quaestors, aediles, and tribunes were all elected by the popular assembly and the concilium plebis. After being a praetor and attaining the age of 42 years old, one could have run for the consul position which was perceived as the peak of a career. Again, this position lasted for one year. Consuls and praetors were both elected by the comitia centuriata, which in practice was dominated by the wealthy.
This system lay within a constitution that seemed to balance the influence of the plebeians and the patricians. Interestingly, it was one where the Senate, made up of former high office holders, only had advisory power in theory but in reality exercised a great deal of informal influence and deference such that little happened without their approval. In a similar discordant fashion, the concilium plebis where the plebeians were represented had a great deal of power in theory — after 287 BC it could unilaterally make laws which bound all Romans — but it rarely exercised this prerogative, partly due to influence from wealthy plebeians.
This divergence between theory and practise would prove to be a vulnerability later on. But initially, the pro-social nature of the elites along with a system that helped build consensus resulted in a constitution which Polybius deemed “irresistible and certain of obtaining whatever it determines to attempt.”
The Roman System under Pressure
But as Polybius also noted, the strengths and weaknesses of a system are truly revealed when crisis strikes. This would occur when the First Punic War with Carthage started in 264 BC.
The war didn’t start well for the Romans. Faced with repeated naval setbacks and the loss of hundreds of ships due to stormy weather, they could only win by cutting off Carthage’s supply route over sea to Italy. But their treasury was empty, and the people were not willing to pay more taxes to build more ships. The Roman elites stepped in:
Instead, “the ambition (philotimia) and patriotism of the leading men” provided the funds to pay for the fleet. Some backers were individuals, others were teams of a few men, but all paid as much as their means permitted to build and outfit a ship, with the promise that they would be repaid only if the expedition succeeded. Roman elites would gain the glory for this victory and, in 241, they did. The new Roman armada decisively defeated the Carthaginian fleet.
Ultimately the First Punic War ended when Carthage sued for peace in 241 BC, despite the fact that it was far richer than Rome. For Watt, the decisive advantage for Rome came from the fact that its elites completed with each other to provide the greatest service to their home city, for which the city repaid them with honour.
But Carthage wasn’t going to give up so easily, and so came the Second Punic War in 218 BC when the Carthaginians, led by Hannibal, invaded Italy via the Alps. The Romans were slow to recognise this for the challenge it was, resulting in then-consul Flaminius aiming for a quick victory over Hannibal in order to shore up his political authority. The Romans failed to win, losing 15,000 men.
Switching leadership to Fabius Maximus, they then adopted a then-novel strategy of delay and attrition, which worked for a while. After getting tired of this and some even coming to see it as cowardly, the Romans switched back to looking for a quick victory and elected a Consul who promised an end to the strategy of delay. This again resulted in disaster, and Rome itself seemed to be under threat. Reverting back to the strategy of delay, they even shifted towards what Watt called an ancient version of total war as around 70 percent of the citizen population aged 17-60 enrolled in the military.
Political support for this strategy lasted for over a decade. When money ran short, Senators and other wealthy Romans lent money to pay for the war. The coin was devalued.
Carthage finally surrendered in 202 BC, but the war deeply changed Roman politics. The military had expanded dramatically, the monetary system was fundamentally altered, and new command posts were created with longer terms so that strategy could be executed more consistently than one-year terms could allow.
Consequences of the Wars
Aside from the significant institutional changes, two trends proved especially dangerous.
First, population declined due to the ravages of war. The number of male Roman citizens seems to have fallen from around 270,000 in 233 BC to 137,000 in 208 BC. But this meant that there were more opportunities per capita for those who survived: for example, after the war there were numerous economic and agricultural opportunities due to land being confiscated from conquered cities. New colonies were also established in Northern Italy.
Rapid population growth followed in peacetime, with around 328,000 male citizens registered in the first census taken after the war. But growth continued past the point needed to compensate war losses, and ultimately farms were subdivided among sons to the point where holdings were too small to raise a family on. There was thus a relative decline in living standards, and many started moving to the cities.
Second, wealth began to rush into the Republic but was concentrated in the hands of a few. Contracts for new infrastructure projects, such as the gigantic Aqua Marcia, were bid on by and ultimately awarded to Roman elites, who made vast amount of profits.
The wealthiest Romans started to invest in land, industrial properties, money-lending, and trade syndicates. Watt describes the example of Cato the Elder in detail. Along with investing in pastures, forests, and hot springs, he became a regular lender in commercial lending and even circumvented laws designed to prevent senators from getting involved in trade in order to invest in commercial shipping.
Another example was Scipio Africanus, defeater of Hannibal. After the victory, he awarded himself 700,000 denarii, an award which made him the richest person in Rome. In comparison, the monthly wage for a soldier was 10 denarii, and they received a bonus of 40 following the victory.
Scipio used his newfound wealth to boost his public profile by funding games and monuments. This initiated a trend whereby money would become essential to the pursuit of public office. The games funded by magistrates became ever grander. Comparable gladiatorial shows went from having 25 pairs of gladiators in 200 BC to 120 pairs in 183 BC. Feasts became more opulent, temples more numerous, and luxury villas and products began to appear.
The growth of large fortunes was persistent: according to Watt, “Crassus, the richest Roman a little more than a century later, at one point controlled a fortune worth nearly forty times what Scipio possessed.” Unlike that of Scipio’s, it was a paper fortune and therefore more liquid, making it easier to manipulate and grow.
And now we come to what is perhaps the most important part of the book:
The ancestral honors and public offices that a man like Fabricius could proudly claim mattered more than private wealth seemed quaint in this sparkling new Roman world of seaside villas, bronze couches, and overseas conquests. The political structure of the Republic still managed to channel the ambitions of elite Roman men toward offices and honors that only the state could offer. But second-century elites were also becoming increasingly enamored with advertising their wealth and business acumen, areas of achievement over which the Republic had much less control. The Republic’s monopoly on the rewards that leading Romans sought was beginning to loosen. As it did, some of the established families who were falling behind economically became increasingly concerned that they could not compete effectively in this new environment.
Efforts were made to curb the increasing role of money in politics. Secret ballots were introduced to render bribes less effective. Special courts were created to investigate extortion and other abuses of power carried out by Roman governors, in order to prevent them from using the wealth so acquired to influence politics in Rome itself.
The growing role of money probably helped families monopolise power. According to Turchin and Nefedov in Secular Cycles, “the proportion of consuls with consular ascendants increased from 45 percent in 249–220 to 64 percent in 139–110. In other words, the nobles actually tightened their grip on consular power toward the Gracchan period. The same dynamic is observed when looking at consuls with consular fathers: from 30–38 percent before 170 to 58 percent in 139–110.” But at the same time as the number of consuls with consular fathers was increasing, the number of consuls with consular sons was decreasing. This is because the level of intra-elite competition was intensifying: it was harder to get a position, so small advantages such as having a father as consul seem to have become more important. But the higher level of competition also meant that it was harder for someone to ensure that their son became a consul.
Recall that this is happening at the same time that many Italians are getting poorer, moving to the cities, and growing frustrated at the inability of the Republic to control corruption and inequality. That was the cue for the populists.
Among the populists, Tiberius Gracchus was initially the most prominent. Starting out as a golden child of the establishment, his fortunes turned for the worse when a treaty he negotiated was denounced by the elites. But it was popular among the masses, so he decided to capitalise on this support by proposing a reform to give a land holding to some of the Roman poor. The principle behind this move — redistributing wealth — alarmed his opponents in the Senate, who refused to endorse the proposal.
He reacted by bringing his proposal to the concilium plebis — a large break from tradition which destabilised the constitution by disturbing deliberative checks and balances. It encountered considerable resistance. Leading up to the vote, voting urns disappeared, fanning the flames of anger and leaving the people on the verge of rioting. When his co-tribune Octavius tried to block it, Tiberius pointed out his conflict of interest as a holder of large amounts of public land and encouraged the people to remove him from office. Now that Octavius’s person was no longer sacrosanct (a property attached to being a tribune) an angry mob tried to attack him, from whom be barely escaped. Tiberius was partly responsible for this turn of events:
Tiberius fanned the flames of public anger by encouraging rumors that political opponents had threatened him and poisoned one of his friends. This sometimes led crowds of angry supporters to accompany him through the city. Tiberius’s household attendants physically removed Octavius from the Rostra, and a mob of his supporters threatened to assault Octavius after his removal. Tiberius never ordered or even condoned violence, but he did make regular use of the threat of it.
But as his term was coming to an end, Tiberius began to fear that the violence meted out to others would come back to him. He told his supporters that his enemies would kill him. He thus stood for a second term as tribune, a move that was legal but unprecedented. In the end, a mob led by the pontifex maximus Scipio Nascia went to the assembly where votes were being cast, a riot broke out, and Tiberius was clubbed to death, along with around three hundred other Romans. As Plutarch would later say, this was the “first outbreak of civil strife in Rome that resulted in the bloodshed and murder of citizens since the expulsion of the kings.”
After his death, Tiberius’s land reform was allowed to go through, but this did not stabilise the system. Tiberius’s brother Gaius followed up with an even more radical vision, but he too was killed in 121 BC, along with around three thousand followers, when the Senate authorised the killing without trial of Roman citizens if necessary to defend the Republic.
At this stage in Roman history, we have entered the stage where violence has become a common occurrence.
Once the Gracchi brothers were dead, Roman elites thought that they could keep the population quiet by providing them with the benefits that the Gracchi promised. However, as Watt notes, the appeal of the Gracchi lay in the fact that they were against that establishment — they identified a politically profitable approach of railing against corruption and Senatorial arrogance. This was not something the establishment could co-opt.
In the meanwhile, however, a small group of families consolidated the power they had. Watt cites one author who said that elite consolidation of power induced “unlimited and unrestrained greed that invaded, violated, and devastated everything, respecting nothing and holding nothing sacred.”
Bad religious omens and instances of sexual impropriety involving the Vestal Virgins only amplified Roman discontent – despite the fact that the economy continued to grow and the military continued to mostly win. Large fortunes grew to previously unimaginable levels.
It was inevitable that someone would seek to mobilise and weaponise this discontent — and this would be Gaius Marius (who would later marry Julia, the aunt of Julius Caesar). He particularly targeted the Metelli, one of the families who had entrenched themselves in the Roman power structure. He accused them of prolonging a war to hang on to power, a war that he claimed he would manage more effectively if he were given command. The tribunes put the question to the concilium plebis, who voted overwhelmingly to give command to Marius.
He now needed to raise an army. Fewer Romans were meeting the minimum property qualification for military service, so Marius broke with precedent and recruited from the Roman poor, who were both the most enthusiastic and had most to gain. This would have very significant consequences later on, but in the meanwhile, the move helped Marius win a string of victories, making him Rome’s most prominent politician in the process.
He wanted to keep this position, but he had no reforms to make and others began to outdo him on the populist front. In particular, some of his allies were suspected of fomenting violence that resulted in the death of a tribune in 101 BC. When they were pushing through a new land redistribution law, violence was again used by both sides to stop either voting or the exercise of vetos.
Matters dramatically escalated when an ally of Marius sent a gang to kill the leading candidate for a consul position, in order to get the position himself. This was going too far even for Marius, and the Senate authorised him to use all means to deal with the situation. He arrested his former allies and detained them in the senate house, but then a crowd attacked the building, using rooftiles as projectiles. His former allies died, along with many other officeholders.
In the midst of this volatile political activity, some of the structural problems facing Roman society remained. Rural areas laboured under economic strain. The population of Rome was booming, but instead of building the necessary infrastructure to serve the greater number of residents, Roman politicians preferred to win popular support by creating entitlement programmes, such as the subsidised grain programme initiated by Gaius Gracchus.
In addition, a large proportion of the residents in the city Rome were Italians without Roman citizenship. These people did not have the privileges of Roman citizens, such as the entitlement to grain. Moreover, non-Roman Italian cities lost out on tax revenue when these people migrated to Rome. There was significant resentment of this situation.
It was in this context that a tribune named Drusus wanted to remove a check on senatorial corruption. But as this would only benefit Senators, he needed a popular measure to pair it with to make it acceptable. For this, he decided to found more colonies in Italy for Roman citizens by taking land from non-Roman Italians.
This triggered even more resentment and in an effort to defuse the brewing crisis this caused, he proposed a massive enlargement of Roman citizenship to all Italian allies. But this seemed like capitulation to many Romans, who were loath to dilute the privileges they possessed. The anger was so extreme that he was stabbed to death in 91 BC.
Their hope of compromise gone, most of Central and Southern Italy rebelled in what would be called the Social War. The Romans partly defused the rebellion by embracing Drusus’s proposal and extending citizenship to loyal allies and any individual Italians who asked for it. Some southern resistance remained, but this was gradually worn down by Roman campaigns in which Lucius Cornelius Sulla played a key role. A member of an old but faded patrician family, Sulla’s main skill was that he knew how to manipulate the emotions of soldiers — an increasingly important skill, as we will see.
While the Social War was happening, parts of Greece and much of Asia rebelled, crashing the Roman economy. Sulla was initially given command to take on the main instigator, a king in northern Anatolia called Mithridates. But some of Sulla’s rivals such as Marius did not want him to lead the war, as victory would certainly have propelled Sulla to new levels of wealth and power. A mob controlled by one of them forced Sulla to flee the city, and the command fell to Marius.
But what Sulla lost by violence he was willing to take back by violence, and he had an army under his control that, a few officers aside, was willing to follow him to Rome. Against this force Marius and his allies could mount no serious defence, so Sulla took Rome. According to Watt, what this showed was that “that the sort of armies of poor soldiers that Marius had debuted in the 100s would choose loyalty to their commanders over loyalty to the Republic if the commander was sufficiently inspiring and the material benefits were great enough.”
Sulla’s declared intention was to make the Republic work again. To restrain populist impulses, he limited the power of tribunes, and prevented anyone who held that position from holding another office ever again. They could no longer propose laws. Furthermore, he ordered the execution of those he deemed public enemies, including forty senators and one thousand six hundred equites, whose properties he redistributed to his supporters. Failure in Roman politics was becoming associated with death rather than anonymity or disgrace, and his actions created precedents that would later be used to build an autocracy.
Another bad practice of Sulla was his willingness to bribe his soldiers. He allowed them to attack cities such as Athens and redistribute the resulting plunder among themselves, as a way to ensure their support and his popularity. As a consequence of this, when Sulla’s rivals tried to raise an army to confront him, they could not attract soldiers unless they promised plunder. Their reluctance to do this saw their soldiers defect to Sulla.
After reforming the republic Sulla returned to private life, but his Republic did not return to functionality. The lack of competent tribunes meant that urban populations turned to rioting as a way to express displeasure, such as in 75 BC. And there would be incompetent imitators of Sulla, such as Lepidus.
Moreover, revolts in the periphery such as Spain and Thrace demonstrated that the Republic did not manage to regain the monopoly on violence essential for governance. In fact, in order to prosecute such conflicts, it had to rely upon two warlords: Pompey and Crassus, who had helped bring Sulla to power. Watt notes that if either of them had wanted a civil war, the state would have been unable to stop it.
Pompey was a commander somewhat in the mould of Sulla. For example, when dealing with the revolt in Spain, Pompey in some instances paid the salaries and expenses of his own troops (until a food shortage made it impossible), thereby winning the loyalty of his army.
Crassus in contrast was renowned for his greed. When he took most of the plunder from an Umbrian city during the civil war, Sulla’s opinion of him dropped, and it was even alleged he personally added people to proscription lists in order to get their property. He frequently stated that one was only wealthy if he could fund a legion. As a way to grow his own influence, he often funded those seeking office.
For a while, Pompey and Crassus essentially shared power and worked within the republican framework. This was an unstable equilibrium. People grew jealous of Pompey — a young Julius Caesar even supported giving Pompey a command because he thought it would incite further jealously of Pompey, weakening his position the long term.
Such jealously came to the fore when Pompey was returning from victory in Asia. Some such as Cicero suggested that Pompey would march on Rome. In the end, Pompey disbanded his army — a praiseworthy but ultimately counterproductive move, as it meant that he had no leverage to get the Senate to approve the various settlements he had made in Asia. In addition, the law giving land to his tens of thousands of veterans was neglected. On this and many other issues the system was gridlocked, mainly due to the actions of Cato the Younger.
At around this time Julius Caesar was elected consul. He saw that enough people had been estranged by the gridlock there was an appetite to build a broad coalition of supporters to overcome it — an insight that gave rise to the first triumvirate of Pompey, Crassus, and Caesar.
He used this support to circumvent a gridlocked Senate, appealing directly to the concilium plebis to pass a land redistribution law. Pompey neutralised their opponents’ threats to use violence to block the law.
The new laws generated considerable popularity for Caesar, which he used to obtain a command in Gaul. But while Caesar was away and racking up victories, Crassus died, and Roman politics deteriorated into gang violence. This could only be contained by Pompey who increasingly underwrote the normal functioning of the political system.
The death of Crassus meant that there was no balancing factor to hold back the rivalry between Pompey and Caesar. Pompey for example indicated that he would prevent Caesar becoming consul while the latter was still in command. But Caesar feared that without an army, he could be prosecuted or even assassinated. The Senate passed resolutions asking both Pompey and Caesar to disarm: an unlikely scenario. Instead, Pompey took control of all Italian forces. Ultimately the Senate backed Pompey, and the tribunes loyal to Caesar fled.
Both men had long been preparing for a confrontation. But once Caesar entered Italy from Gaul and crossed the Rubicon, Pompey abandoned Rome for Greece. Initially it seemed that Pompey would win, as his forces outnumbered those of Caesar: twice the infantry and seven times the cavalry. In addition, he won the initial battle outside the city of Dyrrachium.
But Caesar’s forces were more experienced, which resulted in a decisive victory at Pharsalus. Pompey fled to Egypt where he thought he would be protected. Instead, the king had him executed.
The way was now free for Caesar to establish his dominance. This he did through making himself indispensable to his supporters. For example, he promised to partly compensate his veterans with land that he himself would purchase, meaning that he would need to be alive for them to receive recompense. He also distributed some gold and silver out of his own funds to soldiers and other Roman citizens, and funded entertainment and construction. After being elected dictator, he turned the consulship into something that he could award upon those he saw as deserving.
Caesar would later be assassinated, but his assassins could never manage to get the political initiative, mainly because they didn’t have any plan for what to do after he was killed. In addition, it was clear the Caesar’s methods and benefactions had won the affection of the populace.
Three figures would try to jostle to be Caesar’s political heir: Marc Antony, a consul; Lepidus, who was Caesar’s deputy as master of the horse; and the eighteen-year-old Octavian (later Augustus) who was named by Caesar as his legal heir in his will. Even though he had no official position in the state, soldiers loyal to Caesar flocked to Octavian, who in many ways skilfully built up his own public image. Thus began dynastic politics. Antony tried to discredit Octavian by alleging that Octavian was trying to assassinate Antony, a tale which few believed and only prompted Octavian to recruit more soldiers with a hefty bonus.
While Antony and Octavian turned against each other, the Senate also turned against Antony, and even allied with Octavian to defeat him. But after Octavian defeated Antony, the Senate refused to give him credit even as it acknowledged those who did little or no fighting. Matters worsened when the Senate ordered Octavian’s troops to serve under Brutus. As he was one of Caesar’s murderers, the order was of course ignored.
Antony however was not destroyed, and meanwhile had joined forces with Lepidus. The Senate voted Antony a public enemy, but had no army with which to confront him. They tried to ignore Octavian and negotiate directly with his soldiers to enlist their servics, which only had the effect of enraging both them and Octavian. Ultimately, Octavian entered and took control of Rome, becoming consul.
He then joined together with Lepidus and Antony in a second triumvirate, with the common objective of eliminating their mutual rivals Brutus and Cassius, who were plundering the East with the support of nearly a hundred thousand troops. Once this was done, they divided up the provinces among themselves — Africa to Lepidus, Gaul and the East to Antony, and the rest to Octavian.
But the balance of power slowly shifted to Octavian. Lepidus retired to private life after his legions abandoned him for Octavian. Antony had become romantically involved with Cleopatra, which was causing him to make strange decisions like forcing Roman client states such as Judea to give territory to her and then to lease it back. When an invasion of Parthia went catastrophically wrong, it was blamed on his attachment to her: that he left her too late and rushed back to her, thereby neglecting the campaign. It emerged that in his will, he gave bequests to his illegitimate non-Roman children with Cleopatra. As such provisions were illegal under Roman law, his reputation in Italy nosedived.
Antony’s blunders made it easy for Octavian to portray himself as the protector of Roman liberty against the manipulative Cleopatra. He even extracted a personal oath of allegiance from all of Italy to legitimise that role — as Watt notes, a highly unrepublican practise.
Octavian would defeat Antony at sea and would then go on to conquer Egypt itself, taking personal possession of the lands previously owned by the Egyptian royal family which he would use to patronise Roman soldiery and citizenry alike.
After a series of five civil wars, the Roman population were ready to purchase order at the expense of autocracy, a point well understood by Octavian. Now, he was the source of “freedom from fear, freedom from famine, and freedom from danger.” Unrivalled, he designed a new order in which he was central, but which retained a patina of republicanism. The system he built was sufficiently stable that it survived numerous incapable emperors. While it collapsed in the West, it survived in the East until 1453. According to Watt, it was “as close to permanent as any political system in the history of the world.”
Reasons for the Fall of the Republic
The above history indicates that there is some truth to the old view that inequality or immiseration can undermine a constitutional order. The deteriorating living standards of those in the Italian countryside contrasted with the growing affluence of the elites, and the tension generated the political energy for those who wanted to assail and subvert the Republic.
Interestingly, Watt does not really blame the growth in inequality for the fall of the Republic. Rather, he says that:
Rome’s republic could have been saved if Tiberius Gracchus had found a compromise with his opponents in 133 BC, or if Livius Drusus had managed to get Romans to accept his citizenship extension to all Italy, or even if Sulla’s commanders had refused to follow him when he chose to march on Rome in 88 BC. Even at the time of Augustus’s birth in 63 BC, there was a chance that the Republic could still survive.
Furthermore, he also adds:
Rome’s republic, then, died because it was allowed to. Its death was not inevitable. It could have been avoided. Over the course of a century, thousands of average men, talented men, and middling men all willingly undercut the power of the Republic to restrict and channel the ambitions of the individual, doing so in the interest of their own shortsighted gains. Every time Cato misused a political procedure, or Clodius intimidated a political opponent, or a Roman citizen took a bribe in exchange for his vote, they wounded the Republic. And the wounds festered whenever ordinary Romans either supported or refused to condemn men who took such actions. Sulla, Marius, Caesar, and Augustus all inflicted mighty blows on the Republic, but its death was caused as much by the thousands of small injuries inflicted by Romans who did not think it could really die. When citizens take the health and durability of their republic for granted, that republic is at risk.
Watts seems to imply that an admonition to politicians and others not to abuse norms is sufficient. But in politics, demand often creates its own supply; if the system becomes plutocratic and thereby an object of grievance, at some point a politician will profit by championing the excluded and neglected.
A more promising approach lies in preventing such frustration from arising in the first place. This means finding ways to constrain inequality and to reduce or prevent immiseration. How could this have been done in the Roman context?
First, an inheritance tax could have been introduced much earlier (one was eventually introduced by Augustus). They could even have introduced a land-value tax.
Second, generals could have been prevented from appropriating plunder. As we saw in the case of Scipio, such plunder generated massive fortunes. But a side-effect of this was probably also immiseration, as slaves were a significant component of plunder — around 150,000 were captured by Aemilius Paullus after conquering Macedon in 167 BC — and this allowed the development of massive estates by landowners. At the time of Augustus, around 250,000 were sold every year. Without such slave power, the wages and land holdings of poorer Romans would probably have been bigger.
A third approach could simply have been not to have executed such extensive military campaigns. Did Rome conquer too much? The existence of plunder probably provided an incentive to the Roman leadership to wage war. Victory meant that they won huge fortunes, but they did not bear the entire cost — recall that the entire population seems to have been taxed to fund campaigns. But some level of military intervention seems to have been inevitable, given the instability in the Mediterranean world following the fall of Alexander the Great’s empire.
But the negative effect of the military campaigns is not limited just to death and destruction: it probably also had a key role in the overproduction of elites. Why is this something to be concerned about? As Peter Turchin has argued, it takes more than just inequality to undermine a constitutional order. Some part of the elite also needs to defect from their fellow elites to provide leadership to the disaffected. Such defection is more likely when the number of aspirants exceeds the number of posts available.
As discussed above there certainly seems to have been a higher level of intra-elite competition, which Turchin and Nefedov take to represent elite overproduction. How did this arise? Perhaps the enlarged military resulted in more on the first rung of the cursus honorum, and these people then wished to continue climbing the same hierarchy — a kind of hill-climbing behaviour whereby people tend to climb whatever hierarchy they find themselves on. But the growth of elite positions was more or less fixed until the time of Sulla, who doubled the size of the Senate. These two factors combined would have implied greater competition.
There could be other explanations: maybe nobles had too many children, but not much could have been done about that. Alternatively, young nobles may have become more desperate to get into the elite because political power was being used to grow vast fortunes and thereby lock-in political power. If true, this would draw us to our previous conclusion that inequality should have been contained.
Lessons from the Fall of the Roman Republic
Is there a lesson here for today’s society? One might say that inequality should be avoided. As I discussed elsewhere, there is some truth to this for today’s society. But inequality was only bad in the Roman context because it undermined a previous reward system that resulted in a high degree of social cohesion.
To recap briefly, what made the early Republic so effective was that it oriented people towards acquiring honour rather than wealth, and honour could only be obtained by serving the Republic. Furthermore, this honour was perceived as more important than wealth. This system was effective as long as the quantities of wealth were small. Once villas came into the equation, the rewards of honour became comparatively unimpressive. People became ready to trade one for the other. The real coup de grâce for the old system came when wealth could be used to buy honour.
Such a reward system does not seem to exist anywhere in the West today. There are certainly career tracks, but these vary so much across different parts of the public and private sectors that the common currency used to evaluate one’s social position often tends to be money. Where some structure resembling a cursus honorum with distinct stages still exists, such as in academia, it seems to have degraded for other reasons, such as overspecialisation and working to maximise metrics such as citation counts.
But there would be significant conceptual and practical challenges to creating a similar cursus honorum today: our economy and society is far more complex than that of the Roman Republic, the elite of which was also quite small and geographically concentrated. In addition, wealth was mostly based on land, which was heritable. In this sense it was easy to devote themselves entirely to state service, as their wealth was presumably not in doubt. Perhaps such a social reward system only works where there is already a guarantee of prosperity.
Designing a Social Reward System in a Western Society
With these provisos in mind, it is an interesting intellectual exercise to think about how, if at all, one could introduce a social reward system into the modern world.
One way of creating type of cursus honorum is to develop the template I lay out in Chapter Six of my online book. To summarise that briefly, it is a type of tournament designed to select a pool of people who are conscientious, creative, and somewhat charismatic. It would do so by providing different groups the chance to engage in a common project. In the first stage, done at a local level, groups of 25 would undertake a project. After the completion of this, they would nominate a Prime Contributor — a person who they should see as having contributed most to the project, thereby selecting for conscientiousness.
In the next stage, people with a common interest would take online classes (online, so as to provide for a degree of differentiation in the courses offered which cannot be done in the physical world). The Prime Contributors would get to propose a project related to the area in which they take an online class, which should aim to replicate a technology or cultural work, to master a given technique, or another project which would help increase the creative potential of the young Fellows. They would need to get the support of 50 people within their age cohort — so only 2pc of the population would get to the stage where their project gets to go ahead. This round should select for some mix of persuasiveness and communication ability, which roughly approximates to charisma.
In the third round, the remaining Prime Contributors must propose a project that has a creative dimension, and this must get the support of at least 200 of their cohort to be funded. Those that do we could collectively call the Telarchy (meaning leadership by those whose goal is the Telos – the ultimate or final Good). So only 0.5pc of a cohort would have the opportunity to propose a project, and this right need not be exercised immediately. The project could be of a political, cultural, business, or academic nature.
Now, in light of the discussion of the Roman system, how could we improve the above scheme? What weaknesses could it have?
A first lesson from the above history is that we must always be on guard for the role of money, and its ability to corrupt. Imagine wealthy parents who wanted to get their child into the Telarchy. How could they do it?
One possibility is that they could bribe the people along the way. This could be a problem in initial rounds because the groups are quite small and locally-based. For example, if their child was nominated a Prime Contributor, they could sponsor a holiday or reward for the group.
The fact that the second round is not locally based and involves larger groups should make bribery more difficult. Making the voting process secret would add another layer of protection.
But there is still a risk that the parents could simply find 200 people, and say that if their child is eventually selected as a Telarch, each of the 200 would receive €100 each. For €20,000, they could go a long way to ensuring their child is selected.
One way to avoid this is to simply make it illegal for any sort of bribery to take place. But I doubt that would be sufficient. Where such laws exist, they are sometimes circumvented, as those who enforce the rules may themselves become corrupt and use money as a way to push the interests of their own children. Definitively breaking that loop means creating a group of people without children, without wealth, or without both.
Celibacy as a Guard against Financial Influence
First, we could ensure that just those responsible for enforcing the specific rules discussed above are celibate, so they don’t have any children to promote. However, there is still the possibility that they could promote their close relatives. But as this is a weaker connection, abuse is less likely.
As for whether such a condition could help ensure the longevity of a community, it is instructive to note that among the longest-surviving institutions today there are many monasteries — and this is probably because those who are part of them don’t have any children for whose benefit they might otherwise abuse the institution. More generally, given that the monastery is their only way of having a legacy, they are less likely to act parasitically towards it.
But the monastic life is not for everyone, and the monastic tradition has been in decline. This could have two sources. First, a pull factor into monastic life may have been a genuine desire for a life contemplating God. Without a God at its centre, it is too early to tell whether a Metasophist system would be able to exert a similar pull. But the push factor encouraging people to take on a religious life has also gone: religious orders provided a socially recognised role for those not in the position to inherit a property or occupation. In a world of wealth, this initial push factor may not exist. Celibacy may not then be an all-weather solution, in the sense that it may not be possible to find a sufficient number of people who are both willing to be celibate and to serve in a sort of judicial-legislative role.
A Wealthless Elite?
Another possibility for breaking this feedback loop is to ensure that those enforcing the rules should not be able to acquire wealth. As they themselves would not then be able to use wealth to favour their relatives, they would be less likely to allow others to do so. This means we would need an alternative way of rewarding people — and for this we can take inspiration from the Roman system. Like the early Romans, could we create a kind of social reward that would be able to compete with wealth?
The basic principle for the creation of a social reward system is that the main prizes it offers should not be purchasable by currency, thus providing a sort of firewall against the influence of money. An example of this could be where in return for spending years devoted to the Community, you get the privilege of living in an area or town where property is not available on the private market.
To elaborate this example further, imagine the Community grew to be large and we wanted to create a capital town. You would only be able to live there if you made a recognised contribution or served in a key role. The more beautiful the town, the more interesting its activities, and the more virtuous its population, the greater the value would be of that right to enter and live in that place.
Smaller examples come to mind. One could get the right to access or reside in a certain part of a city — something like the Béguinages in Bruges and other cities in the Low Countries — or just a room in a house, perhaps with dining rights.
It would be interesting to think about creating a series of positions or ranks where one gets access to progressively nicer goods — going from say, a room to house, or access to a better dining hall. In this sense, the monetary dimension of their life would become quite small, because the main needs of life would be looked after. They wouldn’t need monetary wealth, and the rewards they get would not be monetisable. Therefore, they wouldn’t be able to use money to undermine the system, making them the best guardians against the influence of money.
Of course, it is important also to realise the limits of this system. First, it cannot completely replace monetary compensation as providing for the full range of goods a person uses would be overly complex for anything more than a very small group.
Second, the rewards it offers are only as prestigious as the community which offers them. And communities and organisations are only prestigious to the degree that they are powerful or unusually creative. Making such a system works thus means that the community would need to have or be getting control of a significant amount of resources. That could only be done by actively supporting the creation of charitable organisations, co-ops, or companies, which would grow by addressing needs currently unmet.
However, before becoming discouraged, it is worth recalling our initial aim: to create a part of the elite that has no monetary wealth, so they cannot purchase illicit advantages their children. This group wouldn’t need to be large – between twenty to fifty people would suffice – as long as they have the power to ensure that the system is not abused by families to monopolise wealth and power.
Conclusion
The above history of the Roman Republic has two key lessons for Metasophism.
First, if we want to have a truly cohesive society, the role of money as a motivator needs to be constrained, especially among the governing elites. Restraining inequality is one possible way to do this. As inequality grew in the Roman Republic, large fortunes were used to game or undermine the usual selection mechanism of the Roman Republic. This eventually resulted in the norms being hollowed out, and the system being used as a vehicle for the accumulation of wealth and power by others.
However, simply constraining inequality is insufficient to create an effective system of governance. For this, we would also need a social reward system so that the efforts of the elite are channelled into pro-social causes. What was already a somewhat delicate construct in the agricultural economy of Roman times is a far more complex task in the modern economy. But I provided a template for how to select creative and competent elites across society, and how to eliminate the role of money in this selection and as a reward.
Finally, such a system requires the creation of a community that has significant amounts of assets to distribute. In order to create such, there would be a need for a large amount of people willing to commit to a common mission, and creating a model that attracts and benefits people.
*******************
Metasophism is a work in progress — to receive a monthly update on related articles and book reviews, subscribe here.
Alternatively, you can find me on Twitter.
MacIntyre's ethics: justification and metaphysics
Following my summary of After Virtue, I want to dig deeper into some of the questions that arose in the discussion. One of these was how does MacIntyre justify his own account of morality in a way different to Nietzsche.
One of the commenters had the following to say:
Telos ethics is rooted in the concrete relationships one has as embedded in a particular community. Your values arise from your narrative embedded in that community, and those values are not up to you; it is not a matter of personal preference what those values are. So if you play chess growing up, you do not get to decide what the values of chess are. You must submit to the objective values of chess.
I followed up on this interpretation this by reading MacIntyre’s Search for a Defensible Aristotelian Ethics and the Role of Metaphysics by Marian Kuna, and the commenter’s take basically seems to be correct.
Moreover, there were some other useful extracts in Kuna’s paper touching on matters which I did not cover adequately in my summary.
First, regarding why the Aristotelian framework, and particularly its metaphysics, was rejected:
However, once the modern science of Galileo and Newton discredited Aristotelian physics, Aristotelian teleological explanatory framework was replaced by a mechanistic view of nature in which there is no place for natural ends, and so the rest of the Aristotelian scheme could not remain unaffected either.9 The Aristotelian final cause appeared to this new physics, predominantly concerned only with measurable aspects of physical reality, only as an outmoded relic of the past (MacIntyre 1985, 50–61, 81, 83). Therefore, the coexistence of non-teleological physics and teleological ethics became a serious problem.
Once the modern mechanistic science does not, and even cannot, understand physical movement and change in terms of the actualization of object’s potentia- lity toward its final cause, ‘human objects’ cannot be seen as aspiring to achieve their final causes either.
MacIntyre of course sought to create a non-metaphysical ethics, but later abandoned that quest and embraced a Thomist view. But interestingly, he was probably never on the road to success on this anyway:
However, Achtenberg does not claim just that Aristotle’s ethics is immune to criticism of this sort, she extends her critique of MacIntyre, claiming that his Aristotelian ethics is in fact as metaphysical as was Aristotle’s or, as she puts it, MacIntyre’s ethics “has every metaphysical commitment that he imputes to Aristotle”
MacIntyre’s definition of virtue as an acquired human quality, which if posses- sed and exercised by an individual, allows him/her to achieve those goods that are internal to various complex activities s/he is engaged in. Achtenberg rightly points to the fact that an exercisable quality “is at least a capacity and possibly disposition”, and so this definition is clearly metaphysical as it “requires some account of potentiality and act
Should asset prices be included in inflation?
According to Zhou Xiaochuan, governor of the People’s Bank of China (PBOC) for over 15 years until 2018, the answer is yes:
Zhou argues that central banks could adopt a broader concept of inflation, something like the cost of living index flagged by US president-elect Joe Biden, with the measure of inflation going beyond the existing consumer price index (CPI) by factoring in asset prices as well as the cost of public services.
In the euro area, it seems that the only way assets are taken into account is indirectly as rental – and here the weight is 6.5%, which seems a bit low.
What would be the effect of including asset prices on measured inflation? According to this paper from 2002:
We find that the failure to include asset prices in the aggregate price statistic has introduced a downward bias in the U.S. Consumer Price Index on the order of magnitude ofroughly ¼ percentage point annually. Of the three broad assets categories considered here—equities, bonds, and houses—we find that the failure to include housing prices resulted in thelargest potential measurement error. This conclusion is also supported by a cursory look at some cross-country evidence.
Given the large growth in assets prices due to QE, that bias has certainly increased in magnitude.
Society as a symbolic action system
From The Denial of Death by Ernest Becker:
When we appreciate how natural it is for man to strive to be a hero, how deeply it goes in his evolutionary and organismic constitution, how openly he shows it as a child, then it is all the more curious how ignorant most of us are, consciously, of what we really want and need. In our culture anyway, especially in modern times, the heroic seems too big for us, or we too small for it.
Tell a young man that he is entitled to be a hero and he will blush. We disguise our struggle by piling up figures in a bank book to reflect privately our sense of heroic worth. Or by having only a little better home in the neighborhood, a bigger car, brighter children. But underneath throbs the ache of cosmic specialness, no matter how we mask it in concerns of smaller scope.
Occasionally someone admits that he takes his heroism seriously, which gives most of us a chill, as did U.S. Congressman Mendel Rivers, who fed appropriations to the military machine and said he was the most powerful man since Julius Caesar. We may shudder at the crassness of earthly heroism, of both Caesar and his imitators, but the fault is not theirs, it is in the way society sets up its hero system and in the people it allows to fill its roles. The urge to heroism is natural, and to admit it honest. For everyone to admit it would probably release such pent-up force as to be devastating to societies as they now are.
The fact is that this is what society is and always has been: a symbolic action system, a structure of statuses and roles, customs and rules for behavior, designed to serve as a vehicle for earthly heroism.
A lesson for would-be reformers
Some quotes from The True Believer: Thoughts On The Nature Of Mass Movements by Eric Hoffer (1951):
Peter the Great was probably the equal, in dedication, power and ruthlessness, of many of the most successful revolutionary or nationalist leaders. Yet he failed in his chief purpose, which was to turn Russia into a Western nation. And the reason he failed was that he did not infuse the Russian masses with some soul-stirring enthusiasm. He either did not think it necessary or did not know how to make of his purpose a holy cause.
The fact that both the French and the Russian revolutions turned into nationalist movements seems to indicate that in modern times nationalism is the most copious and durable source of mass enthusiasm, and that nationalist fervor must be tapped if the drastic changes projected and initiated by revolutionary enthusiasm are to be consummated.
The phenomenal modernization of Japan would probably not have been possible without the revivalist spirit of Japanese nationalism.
Had Chiang Kai-shek known how to set in motion a genuine mass movement, or at least sustain the nationalist enthusiasm kindled by the Japanese invasion, he might have been acting now as the renovator of China. Since he did not know how, he was easily shoved aside by the masters of the art of “religiofication"—the art of turning practical purposes into holy causes.
Why was early Christianity so obsessed with the rich?
Here’s one explanation, from Through the Eye of a Needle (p. 56) by Peter Brown:
Even for the most courageous, many topics were taboo. Reading the stirring sermons of a bishop such as Ambrose of Milan, for instance, one has the impression that denunciations of the rich in general were a substitute for criticisms of the policies of the court in particular. In a court city such as Milan this was a real issue. Ambrose once had to intercede for a man who was being led off to be executed for treason simply because he had said that the present emperor (the young Gratian) was unworthy of his father, Valentinian I. As a result, social criticism tended to be general and studiously non-specific. One suspects that the evil rich—invariably presented in tracts and sermons as generic monsters of avarice and luxury—acted as the whipping boys of public opinion in a world where more precise grievances (such as resentment over high taxation and ill-advised political decisions) could not be expressed.
My summary of After Virtue
For those who only check this page, you may have missed my summary/commentary of After Virtue by Alasdair McIntyre.
It initiated a very lively and interesting discussion on Reddit.
The danger of involution
The word involution has become increasingly popular in China according to this article (via Tanner Greer). But what does it mean? From the article:
Involution can be understood as the opposite of evolution. The Chinese word, neijuan, is made up of the characters for ‘inside’ and ‘rolling,’ and is more intuitively understood as something that spirals in on itself, a process that traps participants who know they won’t benefit from it.
Everyone in China has the same goals: Earn more money, buy a home of more than 100 square meters, own a car, start a family, and so on. This route is very well marked, and everyone is highly integrated. People are all fighting for the same things within this market.
This kind of monoculture is inimical to the spirit of Metasophism, where we would want people and groups to pursue different paths in order to maximise the probability that we find at least one path towards realising the Imperative.
But involution also results in excessive consumption of resources as competition is focussed on the material. Inducing people to compete on producing poetry or music (not that these are realistic options for most) could be less stressful to the planet’s resources. This is possible, as the article hints:
Subsistence refers to hunting and farming, in which people usually cooperate rather than compete so that everyone can be fed. However, competition still exists in this kind of society — usually between leaders and heads of tribes or families. They’re typically male, and they have competitive relationships with leaders in other villages. What are they competing for? Prestige. So, competition exists when it comes to prestige.
Unfortunately, in the example given, leaders gained prestige by redistributing resources — which is still material. But another way of reducing the degree of imitative competition is to modify the structure of power dynamics:
We used to think that competition arises because of resource scarcity, because of what people call an imbalance of supply and demand. But if I was a village head and invented a way that put everyone in competition with each other, with the highest reward being my approval, wouldn’t I be very comfortable as the village head? So-called shortages are human-made. What constitutes a “good life”? What kind of things are “honorable”? Aren’t these all human-made?
Reducing the role of top-down approval, and the ability for those at the top of the hierarchy to set the rules of the game, could pave the way for creativity and diversity — facilitating evolution rather than involution.
A digital euro and full-reserve banking
In an article in Bloomberg, Ferdinando Giugliano discusses how the ECB is discussing the prospect of introducing a digital euro. After noting that this could make some policies like helicopter drops easier, he expresses some concerns:
There are significant risks, though. The main one is the relationship of an “e-euro” with the banking system. People may perceive central bank digital wallets as much safer than traditional bank deposits. After all, a central bank can’t go bust. So it’s possible money would flock to them, especially during times of financial stress. This could destroy the banking system as we know it or, at the very least, force lenders to pay higher deposit rates to keep customers.
If this scenario materialised, then it could be full-reserve banking by the back door. Many people assume that can’t work — but I think it can, under certain conditions, which is why I wrote a chapter about it in the book.
But those conditions, such as a suppression of the shadow banking sector, are not in place. While an intentional shift to full-reserve banking could result in a more stable system, I doubt an unintentional one would be good.
If the digital euro is introduced, we can expect heavy constraints to be placed on its use to prevent it becoming a safe haven in risky times for significant amounts of assets — this has been explicitly stated in an ECB report on the topic.
Under what scenarios would there be political pressure for those constraints to loosen?
If the ECB started offering a higher interest rate to deposits than the normal banking system (which occurred in the US for a while — see the article on the new bank)
If the normal or shadow banking sector self-destructs again, and people demand that they become pure intermediaries of money (as opposed to money-creators they are currently)
If the euro area wanted to attract more capital inflows
Scenario 2 is inevitable, so I think it would be a inevitable that a digital euro would undermine the conventional banking system.
How many people think life is meaningless?
Freddie Sayers at UnHerd cited an interesting OECD study of 15 year-olds across 79 countries:
UK young people placed second-to-last in the world in what they call the ‘meaning in life index’.
Looking down the ‘meaning in life’ rankings, once you get past the predominantly Catholic and Muslim-majority countries at the top of the list, you soon arrive at Switzerland and Austria. These are both European countries comparable to ours, which are only slightly more religious, and yet 71% of their 15-year-olds say they have discovered a satisfactory meaning in life, compared with just 52% of ours. It seems fair to speculate that their famously strong national, regional and local cultures play a part in giving their children a strong sense of place as they grow into adulthood.
It would be interesting to delve deeper into these results – what do people think the meaning of life is, and is that related to how they find meaning in life? There are some possibilites alluded to in the piece:
Sayers mentions the Extinction Rebellion, which is an interesting case. The adherents here think they want to solve environmental problems, yet I suspect if you showed them a quick and easy solution, they would not be very happy. They want the problem to be hard, because the struggle gives their lives meaning. This is not true for all of them, but it wouldn’t surprise me if it was true for many of them.
Furthermore, “the family is still the primary provider of meaning in life, and Britain has a high level of family breakdown: 28.5% of British 12-17 year olds live with only one parent, the third highest in Europe and nearly twice that of Switzerland.”
I discuss the general question of meaning, and ways to give people meaning, in Chapter 11.
Jason Crawford reviews “Where is my flying car?”
Crawford’s review of Where Is My Flying Car? by J. Storrs Hall raises many interesting questions:
If people needed self-actualization, why choose anti-technology crusades? Why not self-actualize through invention, or art?
I think part of this is that you react against a system that doesn't give you much status. If the social system allocates most status and resources to people who can master the creation of technology and the allocation of capital, but you're not capable of that, then you will tend to criticise that system. And of course, most people are not capable of invention and art, or have never been given an opportunity to develop those faculties.
A stable social system needs to have a way of giving everyone access to meaning, especially those who don't succeed in a conventional, material sense. Valorising technological progress and consumption can provide meaning for some, but not for those who don't succeed materially. In contrast, a religion like Christianity gave extra meaning to those who suffered, and in this way counterbalaced unequal material outcomes. That's my interpretation, anyway. As for how one might give everyone access to meaning in a postmodern world, I have some thoughts on that here (Section 11.1).
According to a study conducted by Tillinghast-Towers Perrin, the cost of the U.S. tort system consumes about two percent of GDP, on average.
It would be very interesting to compare this to other countries. My loose impression is that the number of cases relating to tort law increased quite dramatically in Ireland over the past twenty years, such that it has had a big effect on the price of insurance. There are regular news items about such cases. But I don't see those in the media of other European countries.
In Ireland (and maybe in the US), this problem could be solved by two actions. First, imposing maximum damages via legislation. Consider whiplash. According to one article, "the average amount paid out in Ireland for whiplash was 4.4 times higher than for similar injuries in England and Wales" so "if whiplash claims were capped at a maximum of €5,000, average premiums would drop from €700 to between €550 and €590 for most insured people."
Second, moving away from punitive damages which seems to have been embraced by the US system but rejected in most European systems.
Can we prime people to take risk?
A key contributor to stagnation could be a growing reluctance to take risk. All creation involves risk, because when embarking on the journey you rarely know the result. As Paul Graham said, you might fear creating something "lame".
As society develops, it could become less attractive to take risk. For example, if you are musically inclined, learning and performing the works of Beethoven, Mozart, Chopin, and Wagner may deliver more instant rewards then creating your own musical forms. There is a large audience for the renowned, little for the unknown. In addition, someone like J.S. Bach could focus more on writing music, because he didn't have any of those four composers to listen to, and couldn't be paid for performing their works.
Similarly, as wealth grows, more people are employed to manage it. In a society with little wealth, financiers are few as there are fewer assets to trade. The mathematicians and engineers who become quants in our current age would actually have done maths and engineering in a poorer one.
These are two particular instances of a general problem whereby established paths are less risky and therefore more attractive than novel ones.
But without risk, no one will come up with new paradigms of knowledge and organisation. We need people to take risk to ward off stagnation. How can we encourage people to do so?
A potential answer to this question emerged in a conversation between Jim Rutt and Joscha Bach. Rutt cited a psychological experiment (Dutton and Aron, 1974) whereby those who just walked across a dangerous bridge were more likely to arrange a date with a member of the opposite sex immediately afterwards than those who walked over a safer bridge. The implication in the discussion is that doing something risky raises your willingness to take more risk.
In fact, Dutton and Arron state that this behaviour probably arises from what is known as the "Misattribution of Arousal". Essentially, going over a dangerous bridge induces physiological arousal, which the participant mistakes for romantic arousal. According to Allen et al., this effect even holds when someone is aware that the main source of arousal is non-romantic in nature.
Music can also induce physiological arousal: another study finds that women, but not men, were more likely to rate a man as attractive after listening to music. Interestingly, the study notes that "high-arousing, complex music yielded the largest effects". If excitation-transfer theory holds, the same dynamic would probably apply to exercise.
This may be interesting if one wants to raise the number of couples in society. But is there a link to risk-taking in areas such as business, politics and academia? There is some evidence that becoming aware of the neutral nature of arousal can boost confidence, and therefore also risk-taking, at least in the short-term. For example, one study says that arousal is just part of "gearing up" to do a task, and that this feeling is often wrongly attributed to diminished confidence. From the abstract (my emphasis):
"People's confidence that they will do well tends to diminish as the "moment of truth" draws near. We propose that this phenomenon stems in part from individuals using their pre-task arousal as a cue to their level of confidence. Arousal that is part and parcel of "gearing up" to perform a task may be misattributed to diminished confidence... Participants in two experiments who were encouraged to misattribute their arousal to a neutral source ("subliminal noise") expressed greater confidence in their ability than did participants not able to do so"
In this abstract, we have found what we are looking for, and it's slightly better than our starting point as it is much easier to attribute arousal to a normal part of doing a task than it is to find a dangerous bridge to walk across. In practice, this would be useful on a short-term horizon. For example, if you are an entrepreneur about to approach a potential customer or pitch to investors, you should attribute any nervousness to just part of doing a novel task rather than interpreting it as a sign you are about to do the coming task poorly. That could increase your confidence and reduce the probability you will abandon the effort.
Framing nervousness in this way may help people to take risk. But of course, taking a risk does not mean that it will always be successful.
Climate: is there any hope?
Image Source: Zachary Labe - Siberian Arctic and Laptev Sea Ice
It’s been a bad year for the climate. Raging fires in Australia and California, possibly the warmest June on record, and parts of the Arctic have not even begun to refreeze. Our hopes of mitigating climate change are gradually melting away.
And with the virus, few seem to truly care.
What can be done? The cost of renewables may be plummeting: the cost of solar power has fallen by around 90 percent since 2009, while the cost of wind power fell by around 38 percent. But it will take a long time to wean the world off fossil fuels: even under optimistic scenarios of renewable energy deployment, fossils fuels could still account for around 50 percent of the overall energy supply in 2050.
Moreover, we will be left with a carbon hangover long after the fossil fuel binge comes to an end. According to a highly-cited study, 20 to 40 percent of emitted CO2 could remain in the atmosphere for twenty centuries, enough to substantially impact the climate for thousands of years. The precedent for this is the Paleocene-Eocene thermal maximum 55 million years ago, when there was a sharp injection of carbon into the atmosphere and ocean. According to some estimates, it took the Earth around 150,000 years to recover.
As our atmosphere drenches with CO2, the hopes of many will be drowned out by the resulting political and economic chaos. Sweltering temperatures will dent economic productivity, heatwaves will lead to water shortages if not war, and increasingly powerful floods and hurricanes will ravage increasingly decrepit infrastructure.
In the face of such threats, the meagre changes proposed to date are woefully inadequate. Big change is needed: as a collective, we need to reduce consumption, something which has become an unthinking habit. But humanity is a complex system, comprised of billions of entrenched patterns of behaviour. Changing just one pattern or habit is hard — doing so for hundreds of millions of people is perhaps impossible.
But it would be remiss of us to not conceive of a way to change individual behavior. As a society, it is a capability we need to develop; even of it is too late to stop climate change, there are other threats — both known and unknown — on the horizon to which we will need to adapt. So how do we change a complex system?
To answer this question, it is useful to draw on the framework developed by Donella Meadows in Leverage Points: Places to Intervene in a System. A leverage point is a place in a system where a small change in one thing leads to a big change in outcomes. In order of increasing effectiveness, some of the points she described are:
12. Constants, parameters, numbers (such as subsidies, taxes, standards).
10. The structure of material stocks and flows (such as transport networks, population age structures).
5. The rules of the system (such as incentives, punishments, constraints).
4. The power to add, change, evolve, or self-organize system structure.
3. The goals of the system.
2. The mindset or paradigm out of which the system — its goals, structure, rules, delays, parameters — arises.
1. The power to transcend paradigms.
Strikingly, most governments attempt to deal with the problem of climate change by adjusting number 12 e.g. subsidies for renewable energy, and taxes on carbon and fuels. As we saw in the case of the French fuel tax, this often fails in the face of popular discontent. Number 10 (the structure of flows) is also frequently adjusted, for example by introducing more cycling paths, pedestrianising streets, and prioritising public over private transport.
But our current system finds it difficult to adjust the most powerful leverage points, which is probably necessary to enact deep systemic change. Why is that? First, let’s take point 4 and 5: the power to add, change, evolve, or self-organize system structure. We don’t see much of this in the public sector. Our institutions were mostly developed in the 1800s, and have not changed too much since then. IT has been added to the mix, but we in the West still largely have parliaments elected on a regional basis, and a civil service that reproduces itself through a hierarchical, top-down selection process. I may be overly cynical here, but those who have rose to the top of a hierarchy are winning the game; they won’t want to change the rules. And even if we do see innovation in private sector organisational forms, that permeates very slowly into the public sector. If the lever even exists, it’s stiff and rusty.
Point 3 refers to the goals of the system. In our current system, the goal of the collective is nothing more than the sum of the goals of the individual. But without a collective narrative, many tend to find status and meaning by pursuing professional success. Such success is then advertised by conspicuous consumption of goods and travel experiences, the acquisition of which strains the resources of the planet. Whereas in the past many prayed for entry into heaven, today many pray for entry into the upper middle class and the lifestyle it affords. Ironically, this striving for individual salvation is leading to collective damnation.
The goal of the system is the result of the mindset of the system, which is Point 2. On both the political left and right, this is usually an individualist mindset in the sense which often emphasises the story of the individual without relating it to any collective story. It is not clear if this mindset has the ability to change itself, which could be interpreted as the most powerful leverage point.
If few know how to lever the highest points, it may be because it is quite difficult to understand and step out of our mindset — much like Marshall McLuhan’s point about fish quoted above. Understanding our mindset thus requires another to serve as a contrast. Is there a worldview which could serve as an upgrade of the liberalism shared across the political centre? In this sense I would contrast it with Metasophism, the core imperative of which is that we should build a creative and cohesive society in the hope that one day we may unravel the mystery of existence. This is a broad mission which can only be fulfilled as a collective, countering the idea of purely individual and materialistic success.
But the collective should not dominate, and the individual must be free to choose their own way of contributing to the Imperative. This involves allowing people to form their own stories and groups — without requiring the consent or resources of those older or more senior to them. By preventing the rise of a rigid hierarchy, it therefore has a higher capability on Point 4 as well.
A worldview such as this is necessary to deflate the consumptive craze of modern society — and therefore address the issue of climate change. But the best feature of this ideology is that because the fulfilment of the mission requires the survival of humanity, people might start to care about the long-term. And then, finally, there might be hope of solving the problem of climate change after all.
————————————————————————————
If you liked this article, you might also be interested in my longer essay on the environment and climate here.
Metasophism is a work in progress — to follow its development, subscribe for updates here!
Remaining Chapters Posted
Here are the links, along with a preview of the contents:
8.1 Defects in the Current Monetary System
8.2 Reclaiming Money Creation
8.3 Benefits of the New System
Chapter 9: Mitigating Inequality
9.1 Causes of Inequality
9.2 Public Equity Fund
9.3 Heralding a New Age of Wealth
Chapter 10: Environment, Climate, and Space
10.1 The Decline of Food
10.2 The Failure of Climate Change Prevention
10.3 Geoengineering as Solution?
Chapter 11: Metasophism and the Individual
12.1 Metasophism as a Source of Meaning
12.2 A Model of Cognitive Development
12.3 Reinvigourating Culture
Redefining happiness
This essay by Cody Delistraty aims to criticise the “specific, disturbing and very new version of ‘happiness’ that holds that bad feelings must be avoided at all costs." This results in people trying to portray their lives as a continuous string of peak experiences via platforms such as Instagram. This view has some roots in Hobbes, who
cast happiness as an unending process of accumulating objects of desire, thereby redefining it as a subjective, shifting feeling, predicated on our desires. ‘The felicity of this life,’ wrote Hobbes in 1651, ‘consisteth not in the repose of a mind satisfied. For there is no such finis ultimus (utmost aim) nor summum bonum (greatest good) as is spoken of in the books of the old moral philosophers.’
This contrasts with an older idea of happiness, such as that of Epicurus, whereby:
happiness is merely the lack of aponia – physical pain – and ataraxia – mental disturbance. It was not about the pursuit of material gain, or notching up gratifying experiences, but instead was a happiness that lent itself to a constant gratefulness. So long as we are not in mental or physical pain, we can, within this understanding of happiness, be contented.
He also evokes the the Romantics, who embraced both joy and sorrow. Interestingly, the embrace of melancholy can acutually have some benefits. He cites some studies by the the social psychologist Joseph P Forgas at the University of New South Wales in Sydney which indicate that sadness can actually improve memory, judgement, and communication:
people remembered the details of a shop more accurately when the weather was bad and they were in a foul mood
people tend to make more accurate judgments when sad since we’re more aware and less gullible, relying more on what’s actually witnessed than on broad-strokes ideas and stereotypes.
Sadness also makes us better communicators and persuaders, according to his 2007 study, and we are better conversationalists – more adept at interpreting nuance and ambiguity – when sad than happy, according to his 2013 study.
People in sad moods, according to Forgas, tend to be more persistent and hardworking in complex mental tasks than happier people, not only attempting more questions but getting more of the questions correct than their happier counterparts.
Somewhat paradoxically, embracing a negative mood does not necessarily affect life satsifaction:
Those who believed negative emotions could be useful to them reported the same life satisfaction, regardless of their mood
Handwriting boosts learning
According to Professor Audrey van der Meer:
national guidelines should be put into place to ensure that children receive at least a minimum of handwriting training.
Both studies were conducted using an EEG to track and record brain wave activity. The participants wore a hood with over 250 electrodes attached.
The results showed that the brain in both young adults and children is much more active when writing by hand than when typing on a keyboard.
"The use of pen and paper gives the brain more 'hooks' to hang your memories on. Writing by hand creates much more activity in the sensorimotor parts of the brain.
I suspect this would replicate — but there should be a real exam, as brain activity alone is not 100pc conclusive in my view. It would be interesting to do such an experiment with say a history course or an economics course.
How Metasophism takes postmodernism seriously
Arnold Kling has posted an interesting review of Cynical Theories by Helen Pluckrose and James Lindsay. According to Kling, Pluckrose and Lindsay:
describe postmodern Theory as having evolved in three phases. The first phase was simply the original postmodernism, as developed in the 1960s and 1970s. The second phase, which took place in the late 20th century and early 21st, PL term “applied postmodernism,” meaning that it applied the methods of postmodernism to particular realms, including colonialism, race, and gender. The third phase, which began around 2010, they call “reified postmodernism,” which emphasizes real-world activism.
PL describe postmodernism as a system of thought grounded in two principles and having four themes.
The postmodern knowledge principle: Radical skepticism about whether objective knowledge or truth is obtainable and a commitment to cultural constructivism.
The postmodern political principle: A belief that society is formed of systems of power and hierarchies, which decide what can be known and how.
I’m sympathetic to original postmodernism and the idea that we should be skeptical of anything proposed as an absolute truth.
It is therefore important that the pathologies of reified postmodernism (notably the proclivity for violence) don’t discredit the original. If society is to survive, then we need to reduce our reliance on sacred principles as a way of generating social cohesion. Because in a quickly changing world, sacralising values, laws, and institutions inhibits the ability of society to adapt, putting its survival into question. Arnold Toynbee already saw that as being the seed of decline for societies in the past. Given that the rate of societal change has increased, this risk has grown in importance.
So in contrast to what many think, original postmodernism has a role in helping society survive.
Thankfully, reified postmodernism is very exposed to the critique of the original. If “Theory” is to be stopped, then the best way forward is to propose another ideology robust to the critique of original postmodernism. This new ideology would then be able to apply that same critique pretty mercilessly against the reified version.
That is what I try to do with Metasophism, which tries to integrate the critique of original postmodernism by only holding one sacred principle: that the mission for humanity should be to acquire knowledge and survive, in the hope that one day we may discover some objective idea of good — if it actually exists.
That valorises knowledge and its production, without putting any set of values on a pedestal: an ideology that incubates sub-ideologies, while not allowing any individual one to dominate — thereby forcing them to be prestige hierarchies rather than dominance hierarchies.